Subject: Schmitten in the USA – Verfassungsblog
Date: July 9, 2024 at 9:08:30 AM CDT
To:
On first hearing of the Supreme Court’s July 1, 2024, Trump Conservative Justice’s decision holding that President’s have total immunity for what they do when characterized as “official acts,” and then reading the decision, what came to my mind was Carl Schmitt’s 1934 article justifying Hitler’s murders of the “The Night of the Long Knives.” Same logic, meaning no disrespect to the worthy Conservative Justices!
And seeing in the Decision Willmoore Kendall’s and George Carey’s “Federalist Papers Constitution,” as Carey calls what the two of them demanded, with Federalist Papers No. 69, 70, and 77, repeatedly invoked, by the Supreme Court right-wing for the claim of Executive Immunity! (TP-Read it yourselves!)
In looking for an English translation of Schmitt’s article yesterday, I found this article below. And prepared this to send as well to an email list I’m on of attorneys who oppose torture. Saying I well recall disagreeing with a couple people on it, over a decade ago, who were proposing the fascist political/legal theorist Carl Schmitt as whom we should study as the “expert” on "Emergency Law,” as Conservatives like Jeff Sessions had promoted and applied, though not citing to Schmitt. A position I vigorously disagreed with, as informed in part by Scott Horton’s (of Columbia University) knowledge of Schmitt, as well as my own readings of him. Which is what drew me to the article below in looking for what I recall was his translation of Schmitt’s article: ‘The Fuehrer is the Guardian of our Law’ (‘Der Führer schützt das Recht’). An article I was reminded of with the July 1, SC decision on Presidential Immunity. If 9/11 was our Reichstag Fire, with Bush’s/Republican’s Decrees following thereafter, then the 7/1 decision was equivalent to Carl Schmitt rendering his “decision,” Der Führer schützt das Recht,’ to complete the “cycle,” to justify Hitler’s murders!
Couple that with the Dobbs decision, and Alito’s reliance on centuries old, pre-Enlightenment, English common law, as called for by Yoram Hazony in his book on Conservatism, with those cases preceding even “Originalism” (too “1789ish) and we’re not far removed from Goebbel’s exultation that "'the year 1789' was to be 'expunged from history'”.
Add to that the Heritage Foundation’s Project 2025. A combination of Mein Kampf (basically calling for the “subjugation/extermination (if they resist)” of Chinese, Russians, Iranians, Palestinians, and Americans who “resist,” something almost all American agree with now as to the foreign countries, and half agree with as to the Americans. Especially Trump, as his joint operations with Poland’s President Duda and Netanyahu are evidence of, as “Offensive Irregular” clandestine war, as P2025 argues for, and “Hitler’s Second Book” laid out the Master Plan for Global Military Domination, so that it can be said now: “we’re getting Schmitt; good and hard!”
But this article is one of the best explanations of the “Conservative Revolutionary Movement” (the “New Right”) “legal theory” of today, with its objective of ‘illiberal legalism’ to ‘illiberal democracy,’ or “post-Liberalism” as they often self-identify as. With this showing the nexus between Trumpism, and Israeli fascism: Quote: "If you read Hazony’s work carefully, it becomes evident that his vision for the global right is a universalization of the Israeli settler’s mindset: a religious nationalism that has some key points of agreement with Trumpists and the European far right.
Admirers of Patrick Deneen will see in the Vermeule section below, why Vermeule is so popular with “post-Liberals” like Patrick Deneen, also so popular here:
I will add to the point below; though it was true, that Schmitt "was never a Nazi by conviction,” it doesn’t correspond that he “was never a fascist by conviction.” Which is what he was, as part of the “Conservative Revolutionary Movement,” equally fascist, by Mussolini’s definition, though representing a “rival” fascism to the Nazi’s, and whose political thought is now what is drawn upon for what Patrick Deneen and "New Right post-Liberals” call for as regime change. Using the fallacious claim that they’re for “Peace,” but meaning “Peace Through Strength,” of such a disparate U.S. military advantage over the world, even more than today, that the world will permit their subjugation to the U.S. Which, “fat chance,” is all one can say to that. But it sells well to gullible “Conservatives!”
Schmitten in the USAMichael Taggart, the late great New Zealand public lawyer, once described a colleague as ‘Schmitten’, a customarily brilliant way of expressing his puzzlement at how Carl Schmitt’s ‘dangerous mind’ seems so alluring to some Anglo-American lawyers. I doubt that even Mike was capable of imagining the extent to which Adrian Vermeule, a prominent constitutional US lawyer, teaching at Harvard Law School, has not only been Schmitten, but has even surpassed his master in some respects with his essay in the Atlantic, ‘Beyond Originalism: The dominant conservative philosophy for interpreting the Constitution has served its purpose, and scholars ought to develop a more moral framework’. This article does not mention Schmitt. Its argument is presented as a conservative alternative to Dworkinian liberal constitutionalism different from and superior to the versions of originalism favoured by the right of the American legal academy. In a way the argument should appeal to those who have criticized originalists for using implausible claims about what as a matter of fact the legal meaning was at the time the Constitution was written as a disguise for a political agenda for dealing with contemporary issues that no one at that earlier time could have envisaged. But in suggesting that conservative judges should now embrace ‘illiberal legalism’, a deliberate riff off Victor Orbán’s ‘illiberal democracy’, Vermeule advocates abandoning the Constitution altogether as an agreed basis for legal argument. It is significant in this regard that the Hungarian Parliament has just enacted a law, on the pretext of responding to the pandemic, that gives Orbán indefinite authority to rule Hungary by decree. As Kim Lane Scheppele commented in Verfassungsblog, just prior to the enactment, ‘In short, it doesn’t matter what any law in Hungary says today. .., [I]f this pending bill become law, any existing Hungarian law could be overridden at Orbán’s whim’. It is perhaps the closest legal analogue to Hitler’s Enabling Act of 1933, enacted by a thoroughly cowed Reichstag, that made his whims the source of all law and constitutional value. The Fuehrer is the Guardian of the LawIn 1934, Schmitt celebrated with his article ‘The Fuehrer is the Guardian of our Law’ (‘Der Führer schützt das Recht’) the retroactive legalization of the murders of Hitler’s rivals within his ranks that took place during the Night of the Long Knives – (In Carl Schmitt, Positionen und Begriffe in Kampf mit Weimar-Genf-Versailles 1923-1939 (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1988) 199.) That required Schmitt also to celebrate the murder in the same purge of General Schleicher and his wife, and thus of the man to whom Schmitt had been close from the conservative cabinet that had hoped to contain Hitler prior to 1933. This kind of paean to Hitler and the Nazi Party was part of a two-pronged strategy by which Schmitt hoped to protect himself, given his deep association with the conservatives opposed to Hitler, and further his desire to rise to power in the new order. He succeeded in both, becoming for a while ‘crown jurist’ to the Nazis. But he fell out of favour because he was never a Nazi by conviction and was never able to bring himself to the point of entirely abandoning the idea that there is something more to law than the mere instrument of the political ideology that has achieved ascendancy, whatever its content. More important, though, is that Schmitt’s hatred of secularism, humanism, and individualism led him to view legitimate law as the law that is the instrument of an ideology opposed to these ‘isms’, whatever its content. At the same time, he recognized that in a secular age the only accepted legitimating principle is the popular support of a significant proportion of the population, which is why he was an ‘illiberal democrat’ avant la parole. However, any mechanism would do for gauging the acclaim of ‘the people’ — the Ja of the Volk — so periodical elections under the grip of an Orbán-like figure would do the trick. Prior to 1933, Schmitt argued that in a time of fractious pluralism and political partisanship, only the chief executive can rise above the political fray, the secular equivalent of a monarch, and only he can articulate to what to we would now call his ‘base’ a vision of substantive homogeneity which excludes the existentially different ‘other’. Once this unity of ‘friends’ is achieved the leader can govern by law, loyally interpreted by a homogeneous group of judges. This marriage of ‘illiberal legalism’ to ‘illiberal democracy’ is precisely what Orbán has achieved in Hungary and is probably far closer to what Schmitt envisaged as the ideal political society than Nazi Germany. But once Hitler had seized power, Schmitt had no principled basis for resisting giving his own acclaim to the new order, radically opposed as it was to all the ‘isms’ he hated and that it was determined to eradicate its internal enemies. Vermeule’s authoritarian theoryVermeule, I’m sure, is even more opposed to Nazism than Schmitt. But the position he articulates in the Atlantic reproduces all the elements of Schmitt’s pre-1933 position, including a hankering after some idea of legality, evidenced in his claim that he is advocating a kind of interpretive theory of the sort Dworkin developed, albeit one with a different illiberal content. He also proclaims his allegiance to the idea of legality developed by Harvard Law professor Lon L. Fuller. One might think these claims are disingenuous. But they are more naïve or ignorant and show the radical tensions in his Schmitten theory. Vermeule’s substantive constitutionalism does not engage with Dworkin’s interpretive theory which, like originalism, seeks to show that it satisfies a dimension of ‘fit’ with the law of the constitution, as he requires the imposition of a vision of the conservative good that is determined outside of the legal order. And it is a complete mystery why he thinks that one can have an illiberal legalism that is not ‘content to play … within the procedural rules of the liberal legal order’ and yet is at the same time Fullerian, when Fuller’s theory is of the liberal virtues of such rules. I alluded to the fact that Vermuele does not mention Schmitt in this piece. But I am not finding his Schmitten theory in between the lines. He has long proclaimed his allegiance to Schmitt’s legal theory – and, more strikingly, has gone well beyond Schmitt’s largely vacuous musings about political theology in his express commitment to re-establishing, in a way that he claims to be inspired by Schmitt, Christian theocratic rule. In addition, his Atlantic article, published the day after Orbán enacted his version of the Enabling Act, articulates the kind of argument that Schmitt felt able to publish only after 1933. We will at some point surface from the current public health crisis. How and when and what the new normal will look like, no one knows. But we do know that autocrats around the world are using the epidemic as a pretext to gather even more power unto themselves. In this light, the fact that a Harvard Law Professor has published an article at this time with this kind of viral load in the pages of a respectable journal is perhaps more scary than the virus itself.
Subject: Schmitten in the USA – Verfassungsblog
Date: July 9, 2024 at 9:08:30 AM CDT
To:
On first hearing of the Supreme Court’s July 1, 2024, Trump Conservative Justice’s decision holding that President’s have total immunity for what they do when characterized as “official acts,” and then reading the decision, what came to my mind was Carl Schmitt’s 1934 article justifying Hitler’s murders of the “The Night of the Long Knives.” Same logic, meaning no disrespect to the worthy Conservative Justices!
And seeing in the Decision Willmoore Kendall’s and George Carey’s “Federalist Papers Constitution,” as Carey calls what the two of them demanded, with Federalist Papers No. 69, 70, and 77, repeatedly invoked, by the Supreme Court right-wing for the claim of Executive Immunity! (TP-Read it yourselves!)
In looking for an English translation of Schmitt’s article yesterday, I found this article below. And prepared this to send as well to an email list I’m on of attorneys who oppose torture. Saying I well recall disagreeing with a couple people on it, over a decade ago, who were proposing the fascist political/legal theorist Carl Schmitt as whom we should study as the “expert” on "Emergency Law,” as Conservatives like Jeff Sessions had promoted and applied, though not citing to Schmitt. A position I vigorously disagreed with, as informed in part by Scott Horton’s (of Columbia University) knowledge of Schmitt, as well as my own readings of him. Which is what drew me to the article below in looking for what I recall was his translation of Schmitt’s article: ‘The Fuehrer is the Guardian of our Law’ (‘Der Führer schützt das Recht’). An article I was reminded of with the July 1, SC decision on Presidential Immunity. If 9/11 was our Reichstag Fire, with Bush’s/Republican’s Decrees following thereafter, then the 7/1 decision was equivalent to Carl Schmitt rendering his “decision,” Der Führer schützt das Recht,’ to complete the “cycle,” to justify Hitler’s murders!
Couple that with the Dobbs decision, and Alito’s reliance on centuries old, pre-Enlightenment, English common law, as called for by Yoram Hazony in his book on Conservatism, with those cases preceding even “Originalism” (too “1789ish) and we’re not far removed from Goebbel’s exultation that "'the year 1789' was to be 'expunged from history'”.
Add to that the Heritage Foundation’s Project 2025. A combination of Mein Kampf (basically calling for the “subjugation/extermination (if they resist)” of Chinese, Russians, Iranians, Palestinians, and Americans who “resist,” something almost all American agree with now as to the foreign countries, and half agree with as to the Americans. Especially Trump, as his joint operations with Poland’s President Duda and Netanyahu are evidence of, as “Offensive Irregular” clandestine war, as P2025 argues for, and “Hitler’s Second Book” laid out the Master Plan for Global Military Domination, so that it can be said now: “we’re getting Schmitt; good and hard!”
But this article is one of the best explanations of the “Conservative Revolutionary Movement” (the “New Right”) “legal theory” of today, with its objective of ‘illiberal legalism’ to ‘illiberal democracy,’ or “post-Liberalism” as they often self-identify as. With this showing the nexus between Trumpism, and Israeli fascism: Quote: "If you read Hazony’s work carefully, it becomes evident that his vision for the global right is a universalization of the Israeli settler’s mindset: a religious nationalism that has some key points of agreement with Trumpists and the European far right.
Admirers of Patrick Deneen will see in the Vermeule section below, why Vermeule is so popular with “post-Liberals” like Patrick Deneen, also so popular here:
I will add to the point below; though it was true, that Schmitt "was never a Nazi by conviction,” it doesn’t correspond that he “was never a fascist by conviction.” Which is what he was, as part of the “Conservative Revolutionary Movement,” equally fascist, by Mussolini’s definition, though representing a “rival” fascism to the Nazi’s, and whose political thought is now what is drawn upon for what Patrick Deneen and "New Right post-Liberals” call for as regime change. Using the fallacious claim that they’re for “Peace,” but meaning “Peace Through Strength,” of such a disparate U.S. military advantage over the world, even more than today, that the world will permit their subjugation to the U.S. Which, “fat chance,” is all one can say to that. But it sells well to gullible “Conservatives!”
Schmitten in the USAMichael Taggart, the late great New Zealand public lawyer, once described a colleague as ‘Schmitten’, a customarily brilliant way of expressing his puzzlement at how Carl Schmitt’s ‘dangerous mind’ seems so alluring to some Anglo-American lawyers. I doubt that even Mike was capable of imagining the extent to which Adrian Vermeule, a prominent constitutional US lawyer, teaching at Harvard Law School, has not only been Schmitten, but has even surpassed his master in some respects with his essay in the Atlantic, ‘Beyond Originalism: The dominant conservative philosophy for interpreting the Constitution has served its purpose, and scholars ought to develop a more moral framework’. This article does not mention Schmitt. Its argument is presented as a conservative alternative to Dworkinian liberal constitutionalism different from and superior to the versions of originalism favoured by the right of the American legal academy. In a way the argument should appeal to those who have criticized originalists for using implausible claims about what as a matter of fact the legal meaning was at the time the Constitution was written as a disguise for a political agenda for dealing with contemporary issues that no one at that earlier time could have envisaged. But in suggesting that conservative judges should now embrace ‘illiberal legalism’, a deliberate riff off Victor Orbán’s ‘illiberal democracy’, Vermeule advocates abandoning the Constitution altogether as an agreed basis for legal argument. It is significant in this regard that the Hungarian Parliament has just enacted a law, on the pretext of responding to the pandemic, that gives Orbán indefinite authority to rule Hungary by decree. As Kim Lane Scheppele commented in Verfassungsblog, just prior to the enactment, ‘In short, it doesn’t matter what any law in Hungary says today. .., [I]f this pending bill become law, any existing Hungarian law could be overridden at Orbán’s whim’. It is perhaps the closest legal analogue to Hitler’s Enabling Act of 1933, enacted by a thoroughly cowed Reichstag, that made his whims the source of all law and constitutional value. The Fuehrer is the Guardian of the LawIn 1934, Schmitt celebrated with his article ‘The Fuehrer is the Guardian of our Law’ (‘Der Führer schützt das Recht’) the retroactive legalization of the murders of Hitler’s rivals within his ranks that took place during the Night of the Long Knives – (In Carl Schmitt, Positionen und Begriffe in Kampf mit Weimar-Genf-Versailles 1923-1939 (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1988) 199.) That required Schmitt also to celebrate the murder in the same purge of General Schleicher and his wife, and thus of the man to whom Schmitt had been close from the conservative cabinet that had hoped to contain Hitler prior to 1933. This kind of paean to Hitler and the Nazi Party was part of a two-pronged strategy by which Schmitt hoped to protect himself, given his deep association with the conservatives opposed to Hitler, and further his desire to rise to power in the new order. He succeeded in both, becoming for a while ‘crown jurist’ to the Nazis. But he fell out of favour because he was never a Nazi by conviction and was never able to bring himself to the point of entirely abandoning the idea that there is something more to law than the mere instrument of the political ideology that has achieved ascendancy, whatever its content. More important, though, is that Schmitt’s hatred of secularism, humanism, and individualism led him to view legitimate law as the law that is the instrument of an ideology opposed to these ‘isms’, whatever its content. At the same time, he recognized that in a secular age the only accepted legitimating principle is the popular support of a significant proportion of the population, which is why he was an ‘illiberal democrat’ avant la parole. However, any mechanism would do for gauging the acclaim of ‘the people’ — the Ja of the Volk — so periodical elections under the grip of an Orbán-like figure would do the trick. Prior to 1933, Schmitt argued that in a time of fractious pluralism and political partisanship, only the chief executive can rise above the political fray, the secular equivalent of a monarch, and only he can articulate to what to we would now call his ‘base’ a vision of substantive homogeneity which excludes the existentially different ‘other’. Once this unity of ‘friends’ is achieved the leader can govern by law, loyally interpreted by a homogeneous group of judges. This marriage of ‘illiberal legalism’ to ‘illiberal democracy’ is precisely what Orbán has achieved in Hungary and is probably far closer to what Schmitt envisaged as the ideal political society than Nazi Germany. But once Hitler had seized power, Schmitt had no principled basis for resisting giving his own acclaim to the new order, radically opposed as it was to all the ‘isms’ he hated and that it was determined to eradicate its internal enemies. Vermeule’s authoritarian theoryVermeule, I’m sure, is even more opposed to Nazism than Schmitt. But the position he articulates in the Atlantic reproduces all the elements of Schmitt’s pre-1933 position, including a hankering after some idea of legality, evidenced in his claim that he is advocating a kind of interpretive theory of the sort Dworkin developed, albeit one with a different illiberal content. He also proclaims his allegiance to the idea of legality developed by Harvard Law professor Lon L. Fuller. One might think these claims are disingenuous. But they are more naïve or ignorant and show the radical tensions in his Schmitten theory. Vermeule’s substantive constitutionalism does not engage with Dworkin’s interpretive theory which, like originalism, seeks to show that it satisfies a dimension of ‘fit’ with the law of the constitution, as he requires the imposition of a vision of the conservative good that is determined outside of the legal order. And it is a complete mystery why he thinks that one can have an illiberal legalism that is not ‘content to play … within the procedural rules of the liberal legal order’ and yet is at the same time Fullerian, when Fuller’s theory is of the liberal virtues of such rules. I alluded to the fact that Vermuele does not mention Schmitt in this piece. But I am not finding his Schmitten theory in between the lines. He has long proclaimed his allegiance to Schmitt’s legal theory – and, more strikingly, has gone well beyond Schmitt’s largely vacuous musings about political theology in his express commitment to re-establishing, in a way that he claims to be inspired by Schmitt, Christian theocratic rule. In addition, his Atlantic article, published the day after Orbán enacted his version of the Enabling Act, articulates the kind of argument that Schmitt felt able to publish only after 1933. We will at some point surface from the current public health crisis. How and when and what the new normal will look like, no one knows. But we do know that autocrats around the world are using the epidemic as a pretext to gather even more power unto themselves. In this light, the fact that a Harvard Law Professor has published an article at this time with this kind of viral load in the pages of a respectable journal is perhaps more scary than the virus itself.
|